English Legal History
3/11/2009
Outline

 

I. THE ENGLISH AND FRENCH CONSTITUTIONS

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

II. IDEAS ABOUT KINGS—BRACTON (Mats., §5F)

 

 

THE ENGLISH AND FRENCH CONSTITUTIONS
AND THE THEORY OF MONARCHY c.1300

 

1.

Chronology on Mats. V–54:

Louis VI (the Fat) — 1108–1137, time of Henry I

Louis VII (the Young) — 1137–1180, time of Stephen and Henry II

Philip II (Augustus) — 1180–1223, recovered Normandy and launched Albigensian Crusade

Louis IX (St. Louis) — 1226–1270

Philip III (the Bold) — 1270–1285

Philip IV (the Fair) — 1285–1314, war with Edward I and conflict with Pope Boniface VIII

1302 — the Estates General

1307–1312 — destruction of the Templars

2.

France is a country that is in many ways quite similar to England.  And yet by 1300 the constitutions of the two countries were markedly different:

 

a.

There is no common law in France.  The country is divided into the land of customs, pays de droit coutumier, roughly the northern two-thirds in which each area has its own customary law, and the land of the written law, pays de droit écrit, roughly the southern third, in which Roman law is dominant.  In the 14th century the French lawyers will come to speak of the ius commune, the common law, but what they mean is the law taught in the universities, a mixture of Roman and canon law.

 

b.

There is no parliament in France.  There is the parlement of Paris, like the English parliament, the most important court of the realm, but there its functions cease.  If we are looking for a representative body we must look at the Estates General, an important institution but one that is only beginning in the early 14th century, and which never is united with the parlement.

 

c.

There is no legislative activity in the area of private law comparable to that of Henry II or Edward I.  The closest we come is an important procedural ordonnance of St. Louis.

 

d.

Local administration there is, and it is not unlike that in England, but by and large it operates only in the lands directly dependent on the French crown, the French equivalent of the English ancient demesne.

3.

The question is why these differences.  Let me focus on justice, which in some ways is the best known.

 

a.

Justice in France is a seigneurial matter, as it was in England in the early 12th century.  Whether the theory is fief and justice are one (fief et justice sont un) or fief and justice have nothing in common (fief et justice n’ont rien de commun), the fact is that justice is a seigneurial matter at the county level and sometimes lower.  At the beginning of the 13th century there is no mechanism for getting from these courts to the royal courts, except, of course, in the case of the royal demesne.  The notion of royal county courts does not exist.  There are no itinerant justices.

 

b.

Procedure in these courts is archaic and oral with a feudal overlay of trial by battle.  There is no hint of a jury.  The ordeal died much slower in France than it did in England.  Louis IX abolished trial by battle and replaced it with the Romano-canonic inquest procedure.  This is the single most striking illustration of the importance of chronology.  If Saint Louis had reigned in the time of Henry II the developments might well have been the same because Romano-canonic inquest procedure had not been invented in Henry II’s time.

 

c.

Of course the French king had a court, known as in England as the curia regis, and he summoned his vassals to it, among other things, to hear cases.  The 13th century sees an increasing number of professionals in attendance at the court and during the reign of St. Louis it begins to acquire distinct functions: curia in concilio, curia in parlemento, curia in compotis.

 

d.

The parlement heard appeals from the bailiffs and seneschals, first from the newly conquered south, then from the north, then from the seignorial tribunals.  The parlement was also involved in the trial of cases involving peers, the jugement des pairs.  But appeal is not the same thing as hearing cases at first instance.  The parlement did not attempt to impose a uniform law, but to see to it that the bailiff correctly applied the local law.

4.

In the time of Philip Augustus France began to develop a financial administration.  The bailiffs rendered accounts as at the English exchequer.  Indeed, French budget-making may be superior to English in this period.  But the French exchequer does not have a writ system.  Its functions remain essentially financial, and a judicial system does not develop out of it.

5.

The bailiffs and the seneschals, the royal officials, began as itinerant but became local.  They are officers of justice like the sheriffs but they retain full competence.

6.

These differences in institutions produce a series of differences in underlying ideas.

 

a.

The theory of the monarchy, as in England, is a blend of ideas derived from feudalism (the king is the lord of all), from Roman law (the king is emperor in his own realm), and from Christianity (the king is the lord’s annointed).  By the time of Philip the Fair, it is the second idea that has come to dominate, and we will see shortly that this may also be true in England.t

 

b.

The notion of community may be stronger in France than it is in England, which is not to say that it wasn’t strong in England too.  It begins in the family, where already in the 13th century we see ideas of community property between spouses.  The notion of estates of the realm, classes of people within the society having a corporate quality is barely visible in France in 1302 with what may be the first Estates General, but it is powerful at the provincial level.  It will come to develop on the national level in England in the 14th century.  On the other hand, the concept of the community of the realm is weaker in France than it is in England, where it is clearly present in the 13th century.  In France we really have to wait for the Hundred Years’ War before it develops.

 

c.

We see in France as we do not in England a notion that the only law that binds the monarchy is the law of succession.  This is not the only idea about the law and the king floating around in the M.A., and modern historians may have overemphasized it with the advantage of hindsight.

 

d.

The Estates General when it develops is a consultative body dealing with taxation and treaties, only occasionally making initiatives.  For our purposes its separation from the regular judicial function may be its most important characteristic.

 

e.

In France the tendency toward centralization comes in a time when feudalism is on the decline.  The barons never united in France to oppose the king; there is no Magna Carta, no Provisions of Oxford.  Each feudatory held his privileges separately.

7,

Despite these substantial differences, and unlike many historians, I would tend the emphasize the similarities rather than the differences between England and France.  The economy of ideas is very similar in the two countries, and while the difference in institutions is certainly there, they are recognizably of the same institutional stock.  The history of the two countries will diverge remarkably in the 17th century, but anyone who looks at the two countries in 1300 and sees Louis XIV and the Glorious Revolution is looking at the pattern through the strange glasses of hindsight.

 

1.

To give some sense of what I mean about the economy of ideas, let us take a closer look at theories about kingship.  The author I have chosen is Bracton.  Bracton we now know is the name of a committee, one of whom, and perhaps not the most important of whom, was Bracton.  Most of the book we now know was written before 1236.  One or more of the authors of Bracton knew a lot of Roman law.  The passages on kingship are among the best known in the book.  There are considerable complexities in these passages, not the least of which are the result of the fact that the final redaction of the text was done by someone who didn’t understand it, but I think the main outlines are clear enough.  The trick to reading this text is to assume that the material in italicized square brackets is glosses added by a later author.  This is a quite recent discovery, and the argument for doing it can be seen quite clearly in the first sentence of the paragraph.

The king has no equal within his realm, [Subjects cannot be the equals of the ruler because he would thereby lose his rule, since equal can have no authority over equal.] nor a fortiori a superior, because he would then be subject to those subjected to him.

2.

The first statement of the theme comes at the beginning of the book in the section on persons when Bracton is talking about the king.  The king has no equal in his realm, and, of course, no superior.  The bracketed gloss states a theory pretty close to what we would call sovereignty.

The king must not be under man but under God and under the law, because law makes the king, [Let him therefore bestow upon the law what the law bestows upon him, namely, rule and power.] for there is no rex where will rules rather than lex.  Since he is the vicar of God, [And that he ought to be under the law appears clearly in the analogy of Jesus Christ, whose vicegerent on earth he is, for though many ways were open to Him for his ineffable redemption of the human race, the true mercy of God chose this most powerful way to destroy the devil’s work, he would use not the power of force but the reason of justice.  Thus he willed himself to be under the law that he might redeem those who live under it.  For He did not wish to use force but judgment.  And in that same way the Blessed Mother of God, the Virgin Mary, Mother of our Lord, who by an extraordinary privilege was above law, nevertheless, in order to show an example of humility, did not refuse to be subjected to established laws.  Let the king, therefore, do the same, lest his power remain unbridled.] there ought to be no one in his kingdom who surpasses him in the doing of justice, but he ought to be the last, or almost so, to receive it, when he is plaintiff.  f it is asked of him, since no writ runs against him there will [only] be opportunity for a petition, that he correct and amend his act; if he does not, it is punishment enough for him that he await God’s vengeance.

But the king is under God and under the law.  Skipping the glosses for a moment.  The king therefore ought to surpass all in the doing of justice.  But because he has no equal there is no legal remedy against him, only a remedy by way of petition.  If he does not adhere to the petition, God will judge him.  Now this is a very traditional statement of the descending theory of power, and it is reinforced by the religious analogies in big gloss.  The king is the vicar of God; he should submit himself to the law as Christ submitted himself to the law, as the Virgin submitted herself to the law.  The only problem with the religious analogy is that it admits an element of paradox.  In the traditional statement the king was under the law; there was just no remedy on this earth against him, but the exploration of the religious analogy suggests that the king is in some sense freed from the law, but voluntarily submits himself to it.  We may call this Bracton’s paradox.  Other authors in this period will resolve the paradox by saying that the king is subject to divine law or natural law, but is not subject to human law, or that he is the source of human law.  But, as we will see, this is not Bracton’s resolution.  The question is does Bracton have a resolution or does it remain a paradox?

3.

I’m going to skip the second passage for a moment, the so-called “addition about charters.”  Some have doubted that it is part of the original text rather than something added at the time of the Barons’ Wars.

4.

The next passage concerns the power of the king to grant privileges.

It is clear that the lord king [has all] dignities, [[It is the lord king] himself who has ordinary jurisdiction and power over all who are within his realm.1  For he has in his hand all the rights belonging to the crown and the secular power and the material sword pertaining to the governance of the realm.  Also justice and judgment [and everything] connected with jurisdiction, that, as minister and vicar of God, he may render to each his due.  Also everything connected with the peace, that the people entrusted to his care may live in quiet and repose, that none beat, wound or mistreat2 another, [or] steal, take and carry off by force and robbery another’s property, or maim or kill anyone.  Also coercion, that he may punish and compel wrongdoers,  [He in whose power it is to cause the laws, customs, and assizes provided, approved and sworn in his realm to be observed by his people, ought himself to observe them in his own person.] for it is useless to establish laws unless there is someone to enforce them.]3 4rights or jurisdictions in his hand.  He also has, in preference to all others in his realm, privileges by virtue of the jus gentium.  [By the jus gentium] things are his which by the jus naturale ought to be the property of the Wnder, as treasure trove,5 wreck, great Wsh, sturgeon, waif, things said to belong to no one.6  Also by virtue of the jus gentium [things] which by natural law ought to be common to all, as wild beasts and undomesticated birds, which by natural law ought to be acquired7 by apprehension and capture or fowling, [or] by occupation and apprehension, [as] of another’s property, as where a thing is cast away and taken to be abandoned.8  Those concerned with jurisdiction and the peace [Those connected with justice and the peace belong to no one save the crown alone and the royal dignity, nor can they be separated from the crown, since they constitute the crown [For to do justice, [give] judgment and preserve the peace is the crown.] 9without which it can neither subsist nor endure.]10cannot be transferred to persons or tenements, neither the right nor the exercise of the right,11 nor be possessed by a private person unless12 it was given him from above as a delegated jurisdiction, nor can it be delegated without ordinary jurisdiction remaining with the king himself.  Those called privileges, however, though they belong to the crown, may nevertheless be separated from it and transferred to private persons, but only by special grace of the king himself;13 if his grace and special grant do not appear time does not bar the king from his action.  Time does not run against him here since there is no need for proof.14 For it ought to be apparent to all that such things belong to the crown unless the contrary can be shown by a special grant.15  In other matters, however,16 where proof is needed, time runs against him just as against all others.

The passage originally said: The lord king has all dignities, rights or jurisdictions in his hand.  Some examples are given such as treasure trove and hunting.  Another example is jurisdiction.  But jurisdiction is different.  It cannot be alienated but only delegated, and the delegation must leave ordinary jurisdiction in the king’s hand.  Privileges, however, (treasure trove and hunting might be examples) may be granted by the king but a grant must be shown.  Royal privileges cannot be acquired by prescription.  The glossator came along and made it more complex.  In the first place (the second gloss) he added a justification for the concept of inalienability of sovereignty.  The king cannot give away jurisdiction because to do so would be to give away the crown.  Jurisdiction is of the essence of the crown.  That much is clear.  What the big first gloss does is less clear.  A very great scholar of the last generation, Charles McIlwain, without knowing that this was a gloss, thought that the passage drew a distinction between jurisdictio and gubernaculum.  In exercising jurisdictio the king was subject to the law, but in exercising gubernaculum he was not.  Perhaps this is right, but I must confess that I don’t see a distinction between the two being drawn here, nor do I see any indication that the king’s relation to the law is any different in the two.  The paradox remains; the king is both above and below the law.

5.

The final passage comes from the section in which Bracton. treats of jurisdiction generally.

To this end is a king made and chosen, that he do justice to all men [that the Lord may dwell in him, and he by His judgments may separate] and sustain and uphold what he has rightly adjudged, for if there were no one to do justice peace might easily be driven away and it would be to no purpose to establish laws (and do justice) were there no one to enforce them.  The king, since he is the vicar of God on earth, must distinguish jus from injuria, equity from iniquity, that all his subjects may live uprightly, none injure another, and by a just award each be restored to that which is his own.  He must surpass in power all those subjected to him, [He ought to have no peer, much less a superior, especially in the doing of justice,1 that it may truly be said of him, ‘Great is our lord and great is his virtue etc.,’ though in suing for justice he ought not to rank above the lowliest in his kingdom.] nevertheless, since the heart of a king ought to be in the hand of God, let him, that he be not unbridled, put on the bridle of temperance and the reins of moderation, lest being unbridled, he be drawn toward injustice.  For the king, since he is the minister and vicar of God on earth, can do nothing save what he can do de jure, [despite the statement that the will of the prince has the force of law, because there follows at the end of the lex the words ‘since by the lex regia, which was made with respect to his sovereignty’; nor is that anything rashly put forward of his own will, but what has been rightly decided with the counsel of his magnates, deliberation and consultation having been had thereon, the king giving it auctoritas.]  His power is that of jus, not injuria [and since it is he from whom jus proceeds, 2from the source whence jus takes its origin no instance of injuria ought to arise,3 and also, what one is bound by virtue of his ofWce to forbid to others, he ought not to do himself.] as vicar and minister of God on earth, for that power only is from God, [the power of injuria however, is from the devil, not from God, and the king will be the minister of him whose work he performs,] whose work he performs.  Therefore as long as he does justice he is the vicar of the Eternal King, but the devil’s minister when he deviates into injustice, For he is called rex not from reigning but from ruling well, since he is a king as long as he rules well but a tyrant when he oppresses by violent domination the people entrusted to his care. Let him, therefore, temper his power by law, which is the bridle of power, that he may live according to the laws, for the law of mankind has decreed that his own laws bind the lawgiver, and elsewhere in the same source, it is a saying worthy of the majesty of a ruler that the prince acknowledge himself bound by the laws.

Again leaving out the problematical gloss in the middle it says that the function of the king is to do justice.  This is what he swore to do at his coronation.  In doing justice he is the vicar of God on earth.  But if he does injustice then he is not the vicar of God but the vicar of the devil; he is not a king but a tyrant, quoting John of Salisbury, who went on, as the author of the passage does not, to suggest that a tyrant might be deposed.  The passage concludes with some reflections on the relationship between justice and mercy.  In the middle of the passage comes the troublesome gloss: “Despite the statement that the will of the prince has the force of law, etc.”  Now what is going on here is an extraordinary twisting of the most absolutistic of texts in Roman law:  “What pleases the prince has the force of law, since by the lex regia the people have given all authority to him.”  It is hard not to conclude that the author of the gloss is rejecting the Roman text and saying that the lex regia in England does not give the king the power to make all laws by himself, but only with the counsel of his magnates, deliberation and consultation having been had thereon, the king giving it auctoritas.  This view is confirmed in the second passage, the one that I skipped, with the mysterious statement that the curia is superior to the king and may “put a bridle” on him.  But this is not the mainstream argument of the text.  The mainstream argument of the text establishes a hierarchy descending from God to the law to the king.  The law makes the king.  If the king does not do according to the law he unmakes himself king.  There is no legal remedy if this happens, but God’s judgment will be severe.  In the middle of the century people were thinking of mechanisms whereby they might be able to help God in rendering his judgment.  Wild-eyed radicals would suggest a right of revolution.  This seems to be the argument of the second extract, the one that I skipped.  But most, and I would suggest for the mainstream of our text, the paradox remained unresolved.  It was to remain so for a long time.

 

 

 

 

Download this outline.


[Home Page] [Syllabus] [Announcements] [Lectures]


Please send comments to Rosemary Spang

URL:  http://www.law.harvard.edu/faculty/cdonahue/courses/echfas/lecture/l12.out.html
last modified:  05/02/09

Copyright ©  2009 Charles Donahue, Jr.