TOPIC III
PUBLIC AND PRIVATE CONTROL OF LAND
USE
PRIVATE CONTROL |
||||||
|
A.
NUISANCE AND SOME ECONOMICS |
|||||
|
|
1.
Boomer |
||||
|
|
|
a.
What did the court of
appeals do in Boomer that the lower courts had not already done? |
|||
|
|
|
b. The court does not
answer Judge Jasen’s dissenting argument.
What is the answer? |
|||
|
|
|
c. If we are to “balance
the equities” how do the following
things cut: |
|||
|
|
|
|
i. Defendant’s investment
was $45 million; plaintiffs’ permanent damages $185,000 |
||
|
|
|
|
ii. Plaintiffs were
residential users, not industrial, commercial, or agricultural |
||
|
|
|
|
iii. Other residents of the
area who were not parties to the suit were harmed by defendant’s activities |
||
|
|
|
|
iv. There was no
measurable threat to public health shown |
||
|
|
|
|
v. Defendant had complied
with all relevant zoning and evinronmental protection laws |
||
|
|
|
|
vi. Defendant could not
have easily predicted that it would be held to be a nuisance, but it could
have predicted that its operations would harm those like plaintiffs |
||
|
|
2. |
Coase |
|||
|
|
|
a. How does it work? |
|||
|
|
|
b. How doesn’t it work? |
|||
|
|
|
c. Consequences for the
law? |
|||
|
B. INTRODUCTION TO NON-POSSESSORY INTERESTS IN LAND |
|||||
|
|
1.
corporeal vs. incorporeal hereditaments |
||||
|
|
|
a.
Any legal effect? |
|||
|
|
2. Labels dictate results |
||||
|
|
|
a. right in the land of another vs. estate |
|||
|
C. EASEMENTS – THE BASICS |
|||||
|
|
1. Waldrop |
||||
|
|
|
a. what difference would this have made if
covenant? |
|||
Index: |
Vendor |
Vendee |
|
|
1939 Tinsleys <—Shipmans descrip |
|
descrip town <-Shipmans 1938 |
| |
|
| |
| |
|
|______________ |
1910 Shipmans <- X descrip |
|
|
|
|
|
|
ii.
changed conditions |
|
|
2.
Petersen |
|
|
|
|
a. what kind of an easement is it? the labeling game |
|
|
3. Cox |
|
|
|
|
a.
changed conditions—1945 $8600; 1960 $250 K; c. 3000% |
|
|
4. Categorization rules used to achieve perceived desirable results |
|
|
|
|
a.
successors & assigns without notice — Waldrop |
|
|
5. All cases so far as scope cases |
|
|
|
|
a.
Petersen – contract-type approach |
|
|
6.
Because easements are so difficult to
get rid of, the courts have a tendency to use the categories to move things
out of the easement category into some other category. A favorite category is
“license.” A license is like an estate at will, only with a non-possessory
interest. It’s a personal, revocable permission given by a landowner to
someone else. The person who has a license may not convey it. Indeed, in most
jurisdictions an attempt to convey the license will extinguish it. Like an
estate at will a license is what you get if you attempt to create a
non-possessory interest that violates the statute of frauds. |
|
|
D.
FUNNY EASEMENTS — a.k.a. EASEMENTS ARISING OUT OF MALPRACTICE |
||
|
|
1. |
Prescription—pp.
90–94 |
|
|
2. |
Estoppel
and/or Part Performance |
|
|
3. |
Necessity
and/or Implication |
|
|
|
a.
Plat easements |
|
|
4. |
Cooke — what
doctrine involved (Where two parts of the course come together) |
|
|
|
a. prescription—against state? |
|
E. COVENANTS – THE BASICS |
||
|
|
1. Easements vs. Covenants |
|
|->affirmative |
|
|
a.
burden and benefit |
|
|
|
c.
Side note on “spurious easements” |
|
|
2. Spencer’s Case |
horizontal
|
|
|
The issue is the running of the burden |
|
|
3. The rules at law |
|
|
|
|
a.
formalities – some odd common-law rules; I doubt that any of these
remain except for the S/Frauds with the usual equitable exceptions |
|
|
4. Spencer’s Case |
|
|
|
|
a. privity? |
|
|
5. Equity contrasted: Starting in the 19th century, the courts of equity developed what was, at least for the time, looser rules that would allow coveanants to run in equity when they would not run at law. The extent of coincidence of the rules remained unclear for some time, and, to a certain extent, remains unclear today. One thing, however, was clear, and remains clear today: for a covenant to run in equity, privity of estate is not required; what is required is that the person against whom enforcement is sought must have notice of the existence of the covenant. |
|
|
|
6. Today |
|
|
|
|
a.
Relevance of the law-equity distinction |
|
F. THE RUNNING OF THE BENEFIT |
||
|
|
1. Charping |
|
|
|
|
a.
Holds that the ben. was not intended to run? |
|
|
2.
Richmond — suggests that the ben. can be held
in gross — not all courts will be as liberal as Van Sant; cf. Allen.
What’s all this talk
about the amendment to the condo agreement about? 3. Where are we today? |
|
|
|
|
a.
Charping is good law — there must be intent |
|
G. USES OF A COMMON PLAN |
||
|
|
1. Uses of the common plan |
|
|
|
|
a.
intent |
|
|
2.
What does Riley add to our knowledge? Limited to the situation of the
first deed out? Overrules Cook v. Ramponi? |
|
|
H. GETTING RID OF COVENANTS |
||
|
|
1. |
Ginsberg – almost unique (cf. Abbate) |
|
|
|
a.
Why no estoppel? – estoppel vs. acquiescence
compared; see Camelback |
|
|
2. Camelback |
|
|
|
|
a.
the concept of a buffer zone (perhaps more a product of logic than of
reality) |
|
|
3.$ x = value to burdenend owner of being
able to build commercial |
PUBLIC CONTROL |
||||
|
A. INTRODUCTION |
|||
|
|
1.
Public control of land use - could be and is a course - I propose to do it w/
4 classes - lecturing today and probably at the end — admin. & const.
issues 2. The stat. |
||
|
|
|
sec.
1 - the notion of the police power |
|
|
|
3. What was wrong w/the Town of Preble’s attempt to zone? |
||
|
|
|
a.
zoning comm’n? |
|
|
|
4. Could the town have passed an ordinance banning rock concerts? |
||
|
|
|
a.
stat. authority - see p. 1028 |
|
|
|
5. Why doesn’t this ordinance do it? |
||
|
|
|
a. form over substance - Goldblatt
(p. 1030) |
|
|
|
6. |
How
would Coase solve this problem? |
|
|
B. ZONING BASICS |
|||
|
|
1. |
|
|
|
|
|
a. Euclidean
zoning |
|
|
|
2. |
Pierro |
|
|
|
|
a. legitimate goal of
regulation - motive vs. purpose |
|
|
|
3. Some dichotomies |
||
|
|
|
a.
purpose vs. method |
|
|
|
4. Stoyanoff: What are the issues? |
||
|
|
|
a.
aesthetic purpose |
|
|
|
5. Is this a good piece of legislation? |
||
|
|
|
a.
the poor |
|
|
C. EXCLUSIONARY ZONING |
|||
|
|
1. Summarize the 3 cases: |
||
|
|
|
a.
Mt. Laurel I (1975)—there is an obligation to be open to |
|
|
|
2.
Where does the Mt. Laurel I obligation come from? Due process? Equal
protection? By emphasizing how N.J. differs from the feds on the latter,
court seems to be suggesting that it’s equal protection, but when it gets
through it seems to be a notion of relationship to the general welfare. We
thus do not get involved in the question of fundamental interests or suspect
classifications. 3.
I thought that courts were supposed to defer to legislative determinations.
What happened here? The problem that we raised in the Preble case.
Those that don’t live in 4. What are the mechanisms of Mt. Laurel II: |
||
|
|
|
a.
Must raise level of housing for resident poor. |
|
|
|
5. |
What
does Mt. Laurel III hold? |
|
|
|
|
a.
Delay does not make the Fair Housing Act unconst when the delay is designed
to allow the devlopment of a State Development and Redevelopment Plan. |
|
|
D. PENN CENTRAL |
|||
|
|
1. |
Would the legislation in this case be authorized under the enabling act as
interpreted by the Stoyanoff court? |
|
|
|
2. |
The court’s summary of takings jurisprudence on pp. 1093–94. Note particularly the concepts of “investment-backed” expectations and “physical intrusion.” |
|
|
|
3. |
What are Penn Central’s arguments? |
|
|
|
|
a. Conceptual severance—United States v. Causby |
|
|
|
4. |
Does it go too far? The |
|
|
|
|
a. No interference with present use. |
|
|
E. THE 1987 “TETRALOGY” AND BEYOND |
|||
|
|
1.
The 1987 Cases with Follow-up: |
||
|
|
|
a.
Keystone Bituminous Coal Ass’n v. DeBenedictis |
|
|
|
2. |
The
paranoid planner’s view of all this: |
|
|
|
|
a.
Three out of four cases go against the government. |
|
|
|
3.
Michelman in |
||
|
|
|
a.
Yes, it is true that an unusual number of cases go against the government
here but what do they actually hold. |
|
|
|
4. Lucas |
||
|
|
|
a.
Where landowner is totally deprived of value he must be compensated unless
the regulation deals with a nuisance. |
|
|
|
5. |
Palazzolo – Lucas is going to be limited to its facts? |
|
|
|
|
a. Holdings: |
|
|
F. WHAT DOES IT ALL MEAN? |
|||
|
|
1. Takings Overview |
||
|
|
|
a.
Purpose vs. method |
|
|
|
|
i. it’s not rationally applied - Nectow |
|
|
|
2. Some theory - B. Ackerman, Private Prop. & the Const. (1977) |
||
|
|
|
a.
utilitarian |
|
|
|
3. Legal vs. social property |
||
|
|
|
a.
Highway Dep’t vs. the Air Force |
|
|
G. |
Kelo |
||
|
|
1. Justice O’Connor not
only joined in the majority opinion in Hawuaii
Housing Authority v Midkiff; she wrote it. Did she just get more conservative after 21
years? 2. Now that we’ve got
some better idea of what may be at stake here, can we see how this case
relates to the regulatory takings cases with which we have been dealing? (The obvious way in which they do not
relate is that there’s nothing about “public use” in the due process
clause.) How do the majority and
dissents on this on this question.
(Totally apart from Thomas’s “original understanding” argument, there
is a genuine question, if one takes the language of the constitution at all
seriously, whether “public use” in the fifth amendment as applied to the
states in CBQ means the same thing or something different from the police
power which may justify the deprivation of property on the ground of due
process.) 3. Granted that Berman and Midkiff were on the books, who’s got the
better of the argument between Stevens and O’Connor. 4. What do we make of
Justice Kennedy’s concurrence? (Note
that it was necessary to make up the majority (which included, in addition to
Stevens, Souter, Breyer, Ginsburg). 5. That brings us to
Thomas all by himself. In parsing the
words of the constitution he has one good point (about negative inferences)
and one bad one (the original meaning of the word use). He would neither interpret use broadly nor
would he defer to the legislature.
Thus, he would overrule both Berman
and Midkiff. This is radical stuff, and I think it
unlikely that the court will go that far. 6. Many
states have a more limited eminent domain power whether as a matter of prior
state constitutional law (written in or interpreted) or as a matter of a
reaction to this case, which was quite extreme. |
||
|
|
7. Where are we now obviously depends on two virtually unknown quantities: Roberts and Alito. One need not assume that these men will lead a move to more opposition to regulation. |
||
TOPIC IV
|
|
1. Demsetz (Bentham) and utilitarianism |
|
|
|
|
a.
Property as a creature of the state |
|
|
2. Hegel/Reich |
|
|
|
|
a.
How does Hegel justify unequal distribution of property |
|
|
3. Flemming |
|
|
|
|
a.
Why is N’s Soc. Sec. claim not prop.? |
|
|
4. a.
Bentham/Demsetz and Flemming 5. Shelley |
|
|
|
|
a.
State the holding |
|
|
6. |
Marx |
|
|
|
a.
To what extent is Marx an Hegelian? |
|
|
7. Shack |
|
|
|
|
a.
What is the ratio decidendi? |
|
|
8. PruneYard |
|
|
|
|
a.
The constitutional penumbra of Shack |
|
|
What was this course all about? Some of the ideas that I will try to develop in the last lecture are more fully explored in “The Future of the Concept of Property Predicted from Its Past,” in Property, ed. J.R. Pennock & J.W. Chapman (Nomos No. 22, New York, 1980) 28–68. |
Download this outline as Word document.
[Home Page]
Please send comments to Rosemary Spang
URL: http://www.courses.law.harvard.edu/faculty/cdonahue/courses/prop/out/Topic3.html
last modified: 10/22/09
Copyright © 2008. Charles Donahue, Jr.